TRAGICOSMOLOGY
Algeny,
written in 1983 by Jeremy Rifkin, is a more esoteric incarnation of his later,
more accessible work on genetic technologies, The Biotech Century (1998). Algeny sweeps broadly from the
beginning of biological history to 1983, and foretells the years beyond, some
of which, by now, have already passed.
Algeny,
the species transforming use of biotech, derives from alchemy, the
long-standing effort to convert metals into their chemically teleological state
of perfection, gold. Rifkin predicts
some will attempt to use biotech in an attempt to perfect humans and their
environment. In 1983, Rifkin seemed to
hold little doubt that biotech would be far more efficacious than its low-yield
metallurgical antecedent. He discussed
the much touted recombinant DNA successes of the early 1980s as if they
heralded an imminent and unbroken string of genetic engineering
developments. Advances since that time
have not been as rapid or extensive as suggested.
This
book is all about cosmology. Rifkin observes that societies have often
constructed views of nature and social destiny based on prevailing social and
economic conditions. Thus, rather than
explaining why things are as they are, cosmologies merely serve to legitimize
the status quo. He uses the example of
St. Thomas Aquinas, whose everything-has-an-immutable-role model of nature
arose out of, and was used to justify feudalism.
Rifkin
spends much of the book discussing Darwinism and natural selection. He observes
that Darwin’s dog-eat-dog view of nature arose from Darwin’s study of the
writings of Adam Smith, Malthus, Francis Galton (the father of Eugenics) and
Henri Milne-Edwards and Darwin’s immersion in the fossil fuel-fired
manufacturing economy of nineteenth century England. By advancing the notion that the “survival of
the fittest” was in natural order, Darwin served as a convincing apologist for
the emerging wealthier class.
Rifkin
spends considerable time debunking Darwinism.
He observes that, although for years, skeptics of Darwin have been
dismissed as insane or incompetent, numerous flaws should have prevented
critical thinkers from accepting Darwinism in the first place. For example, he notes that the purportedly
authoritative fossil record on which Darwinism is based is, upon even slightly
closer inspection, far from complete.
With regard to many species, no missing links have been found, despite
over a century and a half of intensive searching. Moreover, he notes many species are
“overdesigned” for their environments, or have traits that developed in advance
of need. Humans, for example, have had
brains far more capable than they needed to be live through the past many
centuries. Similarly, as even Darwin recognized, the complexity of the eye
defies the gradual development explanation intrinsic to natural selection.
Rifkin also noted that the boundaries between species have always been fixed.
While some traits can be influenced by breeding efforts, species transformation
simply does not occur.
Moreover, Rifkin takes aim at the
process of biogenesis the undergirds Darwinism. The notion that earthly
organisms emerged from the lightning-driven fusion of basic elements is barred
by basic properties of chemistry. In
order to prove that life evolved from non-life, one must assume the existence
of a reducing (as opposed to oxidizing) atmosphere, because an oxygen-rich
atmosphere would destroy the chemicals of life before they could be combined
into organic compounds by losing electrons through oxidization. Yet, it’s a Catch-22; without oxygen, there would
be no ozone layer that life needs to survive. And life could not have emerged
under water because the necessary energy of sunlight and water could not have
reached there.
Additionally, Rifkin points out that
evolutionary arguments based on the purported existence of vestigial anatomy
are wrong. The appendix is now believed
to boost immune function. A human
tailbone does not reflect the prior existence of a tail but, rather, serves
important physiological functions.
Further, mathematical models have shown that it is far beyond the realm
of statistical reason to conclude that chemicals could have spontaneously
arranged themselves into even simple organisms, much less complex ones. How unlikely, he notes, that beings bent only
on survival would develop the capability of choosing love over hate, justice
over injustice, composing poetry like Dante’s, music like Mozart’s and drawings
like DaVinci’s.
Despite this, Rifkin noted,
Darwinism still holds considerable sway for at least two reasons. First, it’s been
repeated so often that it has— as do other Big Lies— taken on the ring of
truth. Second for many years there was no other “theory of everything” to take
its place and we all abhor the uncertainty posed by a cosmological vacuum.
Rifkin maintained that a modified,
“temporal” cosmology was emerging. In
this view, species were stable for long periods before changing rapidly in
response to environmental cataclysmal.
Whether or not temporalism and punctuated equilibrium turn out to be
true, it serves, as did the cosmologies before it, to justify an approach
toward nature, society, and economy.
And whether or not temporalism is
the basis for the pursuit of biotech, it seems likely that, for more basic
reasons that Rifkin offers, that society will actively experiment with
biotech. Principally, as Rifkin points
out, humans are afraid to die and have come to view themselves as machines. (I
would add that they like to make money products, and they suspect biotech will yield
bankable products.) Rifkin also observes
that a fundamental tenet of temporalism is that life will increasingly be
viewed as packages of information. The confluence of genomics and computers
will enable the this information to be analyzed to the point that living things
and their consciousnesses can be not only “improved”, but stored, and even
shipped, like so much data.
Rifkin emphasizes that as life
becomes more of a commodity, we will lose a sense of its sacredness and respect
for it. Rifkin observes that this
desacralization will leave us without the companionship of the natural world
that we have always had. (Before that
happens, I suppose biotech could also fail in a more directly observable way,
if scientists could do a bad job and inadvertently cause
bio-catastrophes). But Rifkin laments
that people will be so enticed by the ostensible benefits of this work that
they won’t be able to avoid the Promethean journey.